Randomness and Functional change
Defining what is
meant by ‘random’ is itself a major field of enquiry in
mathematics, computation and in science generally. The
question whether there are truly random events in the
universe is a vexed one, lying at the heart of theories of
quantum mechanics. Probably, we will never know, perhaps
cannot know in principle, the answer to that kind of
question. But it
warns us that defining randomness is not easy. I also say
that in the lectures.
The best way to
sidestep the deeper problems is to ask the question ‘random
with respect to what?’ In evolutionary theory that makes the
problem much simpler. Both Neo-darwinists and their
opponents can then agree that what is really meant is
‘random with respect to physiological (phenotypic)
function’. That is so because one of the central tenets of
Neo-darwinism is the exclusion of any form of Lamarckism,
the idea that function, or functional improvement, can
influence inheritance, i.e. the inheritance of acquired
characteristics. By contrast, a Lamarckian must maintain
that at least some changes are not completely random with
respect to function.
In the article, and
inevitably in much shorter form in the lectures, I approach
this question in three stages. The
first stage is to
establish that genomic change is not random with respect to
location in the genome. The reason for asking that question
first is that without establishing that there are preferred
locations of change, the argument for any kind of
functionally-relevant change cannot even get off the ground.
The only way in which such a change can occur is through
influencing the physical and chemical properties of the
genetic material. Preferred locations of change are
therefore a pre-condition for functional change to be
possible. If all locations in the genome were equipotent for
changes there would be no possibility for
functionally-relevant change.
Of course,
demonstrating the existence of hotspots and other ways in
which change is not randomly distributed with respect to
location does not, in and of itself, demonstrate any form of
functionally-relevant change. The existence of hotspots
could be simply a consequence of the physico-chemical
properties of the genome and its associated proteins even if
no functionally-relevant changes occur. Further
experimentation is required to demonstrate that. I also make
that clear in the article and lectures.
The
second stage in
the argument is to note that well-documented examples of
functionally-relevant genomic change already exist. The
best-investigated case is the evolution of lymphocytes. In
response to antigen activation the relevant part of the
genome undergoes very rapid proliferation. Targeted
speeding-up of change is therefore one mechanism by which
functional change can occur. That is true even if the
individual changes at that location are random. The
functionality lies in the targeting of the location. A
similar targeting occurs in P element homing. And targeted
reorganisation of the genome by speeding up change in
selected locations occurs in bacteria subject to starvation.
All these mechanisms are referred to in the item
Relevance to physiology.
The
third stage in the
argument is experimental demonstration that the inheritance
of acquired characteristics occurs. There are now many
examples of that. See
Transgenerational Inheritance.
Those experimental results require functional
inherited change, either genetically or epigenetically, even
if we do not yet know the molecular mechanisms. All these
stages of the argument are necessary. Some of the critics
have mistaken the first step for the whole argument!
| |
The MUSIC of Life: Biology Beyond the Genome ©Denis Noble |