Slippery definitions: how neo-darwinism accommodates contrary findings
There is a long
history to this. There have been many points at which
neo-darwinism has been challenged experimentally. The
reactions can be characterised as a mixture of assimilation
and denial.
An early example of
assimilation is the reaction to the work of Conrad
Waddington who first coined the term ‘epigenetics’.
Waddington showed that an acquired characteristic in fruit
flies could be assimilated after a number of generations of
selection for the trait. After that it became inheritable in
the standard way without the environmental stimulus that
caused the character to be acquired. In the
Experimental Physiology article I write
The Modern Synthesists should not
have dismissed Waddington’s experiments, for example, as
simply ‘a special case of the evolution of phenotypic
plasticity’ (Arthur, 2010). Of course, the Modern Synthesis
can account for the inheritance of the potential for
plasticity, but what it cannot allow is the inheritance of a
specific acquired form of that plasticity. Waddington’s
experiments demonstrate precisely inheritance of specific
forms of acquired characteristics, as he claimed himself in
the title of his paper (Waddington, 1942). After all, the
pattern of the genome is as much inherited as its individual
components, and those patterns can be determined by the
environment.
Notice that this also
illustrates how neo-darwinism tends to be slippery when it
defines a gene. Defining genes as individual protein-coding
sequences ignores inheritance of characteristics that depend
on the pattern of
the genome. Waddington’s experiments show that it is
perfectly plausible that a characteristic first arises
through environmentally-induced change and then becomes
‘locked in’ to the genome pattern so that it becomes
standard genomic inheritance. No mutations would be required
and the characteristic could appear in a substantial
fraction of the population rather than a single individual.
We don’t know how often this process may have occurred
during evolution. I suspect that many of the additional
mechanisms of variation may become ‘locked in’ in this way.
A ‘gene’ in this
sense can be a new combination of alleles that allows a new
phenotype to develop. The mistake is to ‘atomise’ the
concept of a gene. That is another important difference
between the original definition in terms of phenotypes and
the molecular biological definition in terms of ‘atomised’
DNA elements.
An example of what I
would call denial is provided by an exchange during the 2009
Oxford
debate
that I chaired between Margulis and Dawkins. The transcript
includes Dawkins’ reaction to the example of cellular
inheritance independent of the genome in
Paramecium:
"One example you might have meant
is Sonneborn’s Paramecium where you cut a bit of the
pellicle [ciliate cortex] and twist it ‘round. Well, if
that’s true, and is indeed a non-DNA form of heredity,
that’s absolutely fine. I would embrace that gladly as a new
“honorary” gene. That’s fine. [Groans from the audience] Why
not, why not?" (transcript,
page 21)
The groans from the
audience surely indicate something slippery here. I’d call
it 'having it both ways'. The whole point of the discussion
was whether inheritance is determined by genes alone. Sure,
we can go on redefining 'gene' until we have exhausted all
the possibilities. But a statement that says everything also
says nothing. The denial here is a denial of a
counter-example to neo-darwinism by redefining what is meant
by a gene. As I explain in the lectures the central
confusion lies precisely in the slippage between defining
genes as DNA sequences and their original definition in
terms of inheritable phenotypes. Defined as the latter,
there can, by
definition, be no exceptions. Defined as the former,
there clearly are exceptions.
The relevant slide in
the lecture is:
Relations between genes, environment and phenotype
characters according to current physiological and
biochemical understanding This diagram represents the
interaction between genes (DNA sequences), environment and
phenotype as occurring through biological networks. The
causation occurs in both directions between all three
influences on the networks. This view is very different from
the idea that genes ‘cause’ the phenotype (right hand
arrow). This diagram also helps to explain the difference
between the original concept of a gene as the cause of a
particular phenotype and the modern definition as a DNA
sequence. For further description and analysis of the ideas
behind this diagram see Kohl et al. (2010)
Clinical Pharmacology
and Therapeutics
88, 25–33 .
The sense in which
neo-darwinism has been falsified in this case is precisely
that epigenetic inheritance shows that characteristics of
the biological networks can be inherited independently of
DNA.
Examples
of that are now rapidly accumulating.
Are these kinds of
confusions still occurring? A recent example is provided by
Zuk et al (2012) The mystery of
missing heritability: Genetic interactions create phantom
heritability. PNAS, 109, 1193-1198.
which contains an
equivalent to Dawkins’ invention of ‘honorary gene’ by
inventing the term ‘phantom heritability’. In this case, the
interactions that necessarily include the biological
networks are apparently assimilated into standard genetics
(hence the term ‘genetic
interactions’), when in fact there must be much more
inherited than the relevant DNA sequences. The authors write
“In short, missing heritability need not directly correspond
to missing variants, because current estimates of total
heritability may be significantly inflated by genetic
interactions.” The matter should not be closed off in this
way since the question whether this does or does not involve
inheritance of epigenetic effects must remain open to
further experimentation. And it would be better to recognise
this by avoiding terms like ‘genetic interactions’ that
leave it unclear what precisely is involved but which also
prejudice the conclusion in favour of standard genetic
inheritance.
Redefinition of the
central entity in neo-darwinism, i.e. the ‘gene’, leads to
unintended consequences. Admitting ‘honorary’ or ‘phantom’
genes that refer entirely or partly to cytoplasmic
inheritance makes nonsense of the distinction between
‘replicator’ and ‘vehicle’. The ‘vehicle’ becomes part of
the ‘replicator’.
It is anyway! See
Immortal genes.
| |
The MUSIC of Life: Biology Beyond the Genome ©Denis Noble |